Categories
Books Coding R

The Monty Hall Problem

I just finished the book “The Monty Hall Problem” by Jason Rosenhouse, which is an exploration of one of the most counter intuitive puzzles in probability. The entire book is devoted to the basic form of the problem and a number of variations, of increasing complexity.

The basic outline of the problem is as follows. You are on a game show and are presented with three closed doors. Behind one of the doors is a prize (say a car) and behind the other two doors is nothing. You are asked to select a door. Once you have picked one of the three doors, the game show host (Monty) opens one of the other doors to reveal that it is empty. Your choice is then to either stick with the door you have initially selected or to change your selection to the other unopened door.

So for example, say you select door 1 below and Monty opens door 2. He then offers you the choice to switch to door 3 or stay with your original selection door 1. You have a choice of two unopened doors. Does it make any difference if you switch or stay?

Most people, myself included, will intuitively say no – there are two doors, and the prize has an equal probability of being behind either of the two remaining doors, so the probability is $\frac{1}{2}$ – switching or sticking makes no difference to the odds of winning the prize. However, this is not the case. Switching to the remaining unopened door will result in a win with a probability of $\frac{2}{3}$. This is a very surprising result and in order to understand why we need to look at the mechanics of the game.

We can prove this very quickly using a simulated approach. If we define the rules of the game as follows:

  • The prize can be behind any door with equal initial probability;
  • Monty will never open the door containing the prize;
  • When Monty has a choice of 2 (empty) doors to open, he will randomly choose between them.

Here is a simple R function that we can use to execute a single run of the game. It simulates the simple game given the rules above, and returns a string describing the winning strategy for that game. For example it will return “Stick” if the winning strategy for that game is to stay with the door you initially selected.

classic_monty <- function() {
  # Assign the prize
  prize <- sample(1:3,1)
  # Pick a door
  choice <- sample(1:3,1)
  # Monty picks a door
  monty <- sample(c(1:3)[-c(choice,prize)], 1)
  return(ifelse(prize!=choice, "Switch", "Stick"))
}

We can run the game a few times and see the result:

> classic_monty()
[1] "Switch"
> classic_monty()
[1] "Stick"
> classic_monty()
[1] "Switch"

To see the asymptotic win probability of switch or stick, we can replicate the experiment a number of times and record the outcome:

n <- 2^(1:16)
runs <- data.frame(n=numeric(), switch=numeric())
for (trials in n) {
  run <- table(replicate(trials, classic_monty()))
  runs <- runs %>%  add_row(n=trials, switch=(sum(run["Switch"]))/trials)
}
# Handle zero-occurrence trials
runs[is.na(runs)]<-0

If we run this, then we can examine the win probability using the switch strategy as we increase the number of trials:

> runs
       n    switch
1      2 0.0000000
2      4 0.2500000
3      8 0.6250000
4     16 0.5000000
5     32 0.5937500
6     64 0.7031250
7    128 0.6640625
8    256 0.6835938
9    512 0.6484375
10  1024 0.6640625
11  2048 0.6748047
12  4096 0.6645508
13  8192 0.6702881
14 16384 0.6721191
15 32768 0.6636963
16 65536 0.6641541

There is a clear convergence to a $\frac{2}{3}$ win probability using the switch strategy. This is something I had to simulate to initially accept, as my intuitive expectation was a win probability of $\frac{1}{2}$.

In order to understand the mechanics behind this result a little more, we can generate the full space of possible outcomes $ \left( C, M, P\right) $for each trial, where $C$ is the door we choose, $M$ is the door Monty opens, and $P$ is the door that hides the prize. For example the tuple $\left( 1, 2, 3\right)$ would be the scenario where we pick door 1, Monty reveals door 2, and the prize sits behind door 3.

The code to generate the sample space is below:

# Generate sample space of tuples for Monty-Hall 
space <- data.frame(choice=numeric(), monty=numeric(), prize=numeric())

i <- 1
for (prize in 1:3) {
 for (choice in 1:3) {
    for (monty in c(1:3)[-c(prize,choice)]) {
      space <- space %>%  add_row(choice=choice,monty=monty,prize=prize)
    }
  }
}

space <- space %>% arrange(choice)

Which will generate a table as follows:

> head(space)
  choice monty prize
1      1     2     1
2      1     3     1
3      1     3     2
4      1     2     3
5      2     3     1
6      2     1     2

Let’s look at a sample play. Say we choose door 1. The sample space for possible plays where we choose door 1 is:

1      1     2     1
2      1     3     1
3      1     3     2
4      1     2     3

So if we stick with door 1 it looks like we have 2 outcomes out of 4, or a 50% chance of winning. However this is not the case, as the first two rows in the sample space above must have the same probability as each of the last two rows – door 1 has a fixed probability of $\frac{1}{3}$ of hiding the prize and that cannot change. So the first two outcomes above have a combined probability of $\frac{1}{3}$, which means that the win probability when switching is $\frac{2}{3}$.

Once we see the sample space enumerated like this, the reason for the switch probability seems obvious – due to the rules of the game outlined above, we have constrained the sample space. If the host follows the rules above and randomly chooses between two unopened doors when we have selected the door with the prize, but in all other cases will only open the door that is empty, we can see that the choice of door opened by Monty contains information – which is why his choice of door is important.

The Bayesian Approach

As an aside, the book contains a short conditional probability-based approach to the simple scenario above that I think is worth showing. If $C_n$ denotes that the prize is behind door $n$ and $M_m$ denotes that Monty opens door $m$, then assuming we choose door 1 as above and Monty then opens door 2 – we can ask the question what is the probability now that the prize is behind door 3 – i.e. $P(C_3|M_2)$?

This is $P(C_3|M_2) = \frac{P(M_2|C_3)P(C_3)}{P(M_2)}$

$=\frac{P(M_2|C_3)P(C_3)}{P(M_2|C_1)P(C_1)+P(M_2|C_2)P(C_2)+P(M_2|C_3)P(C_3)}$

We can infer that if any door is initially likely to contain the prize, then

$P(C_1)=P(C_2)=P(C_3)=\frac{1}{3}$

And as Monty will not open the door hiding the prize $P(M_2|C_2)=0$, and will be forced to open the only remaining door if we have chosen door 1 and the prize is behind door 3, then $P(M_2|C_3)=1$

This then simplifies to

$P(C_3|M_2) = \frac{1}{P(M_2|C_1)+1}$

We can figure out $P(M_2|C_1)$ using the simple rules of the game – if we have selected door 1 and the prize is behind door 1, Monty must choose randomly between the other two doors. So $P(M_2|C_1)=P(M_3|C_1)=\frac{1}{2}$.

Thus

$P(C_3|M_2) = \frac{2}{3}$

Another nice approach. This is a nice problem to illustrate just how deceptive simple probability puzzles can be!

Categories
Books Finance

Financial Amnesia

The FT has a nice article on financial amnesia, which talks about the desire of the CFA UK discipline to incorporate some financial history into their curriculum, ostensibly to implant enough of a sense of deja vu in budding financial managers when they encounter potential disaster scenarios that they may avoid repeating them.

I think this is a great idea – the only problem is that it probably wont have any sort of meaningful impact other than provide some fascinating course material for CFA students. The problem with an industry that makes its living from markets that essentially operate on two gears – fear and greed – is that despite all of the prior knowledge in the world, we will willingly impose a state of amnesia upon ourselves if we can convince ourselves that what is happening now is in some way different, or just different enough from whatever disasters happened before. The Internet bubble, tulip-mania, and the various property boom and busts that we have seen over the last decade share at their core a common set of characteristics, but they are different (or “new”) enough that we were able to live in a state of denial. The “fear and greed” mentality also means that even if you know you are operating in a bubble that will eventually burst, you carry on regardless, as you plan to be out of the game before it all goes bad (The Greater Fool theory).

Incidentally, if you want to read a beautifully written and entertaining account of financial bubbles by one of the greatest writers on this topic, you should read this book (“A Short History of Financial Euphoria” by J.K. Galbraith). It packs a huge amount of wit and insight into its relatively small page count.

NOTE: Galbraith also wrote the definitive account on the Great Crash of 1929, which rapidly became required reading around three years ago…it’s also excellent. Galbraith has a beautiful turn of phrase.